When you see a ripe lemon in a supermarket, it seems eminently reasonable for you to believe that a lemon is there. Here you have a perceptual experience since you consciously see something yellow. And your experience seems to justify your belief since your experience seems to make it reasonable for you to believe that a lemon is there.
Our perceptual experiences of the world outside us seem to justify our beliefs about how the world outside us is. If that’s right, a question in the epistemology of perception remains open: how do our experiences justify beliefs about the external world? And a question in the philosophy of mind remains open as well: what are our experiences themselves like?
This entry will survey interactions between the epistemology of perception and the philosophy of mind. Following the existing literature, the focus will be on visual perceptual experience. The reader is invited to consider how generalizations to other senses might or might not succeed.
Section 1 considers theories of experience and what implications they might have for the epistemology of perception. Section 2 considers perceptual phenomena, such as attending or dreaming, with special implications for the epistemology of perception.
For our purposes, a theory of perceptual experience aims to identify a feature that is constitutive of perceptual experience: it is shared by all perceptual experiences, and identifies at least part of their nature. In this section, we will consider various potential links between theories of experience and the epistemology of perception that can be captured with the following template:
Epistemology-Mind Link
If experiences justify beliefs about the external world, then experiences have property \(P\).
The idea here is that experiences have to be a certain way in order to justify beliefs. Now, philosophers might accept a particular instance of the E-M Link, but disagree about whether experiences are the way they need to be in order to justify beliefs about the external world. For example, Davidson (1986) and McDowell (1994) agree that experiences justify beliefs about the external world only if experiences have contents that can be assessed for truth. Davidson (1986) argues that experiences do not justify beliefs about the external world on the grounds that they lack truth-assessable contents, whereas McDowell (1994) argues that experiences must have truth-assessable contents given that they justify beliefs about the external world (more on their dispute in subsection 1.2).
We can organize our discussion of such agreements and disagreements around the following trio of claims:
Epistemology
Our experiences justify beliefs about the external world.
Epistemology-Mind Link
If our experiences justify beliefs about the external world, then our experiences have property \(P\).
Mind
Our experiences do not have property \(P\).
If Epistemology and Epistemology-Mind Link are true, then Mind is false. Something will have to go. Approaches will vary according to their verdict on what exactly must go.
In what follows we survey the most prominent instances of the trio. We will start with sense-data theories, then turn to raw feel theories, and theories on which experiences have propositional contents. We will close the part by considering the conscious character of experiences.
Our survey of theories of experiences will not be exhaustive, but I will briefly discuss an approach that complicates my framing of the debates in terms of “visual experiences”. Some have argued that, when the ordinary shopper observes the lemon in the supermarket, her visual mental life is not as simple as it seems. In particular, rather than having a unitary visual experience, perhaps she has a visual sensation and a visual seeming (Lyons 2005; Tucker 2010; Brogaard 2013; Reiland 2015; also Bengson 2015 as a fellow traveler). Call this the “hybrid” picture of experience.
To get a feel for the hybrid picture, consider a contrast between an expert bird-watcher and an ordinary perceiver, both observing a northern bobwhite. The hybrid theorist would say that they have the same rudimentary visual sensation in some way involving colors and shapes, with only the expert has a visual seeming specifically to the effect that a northern bobwhite is present. Here the visual sensation shared by the expert and novice is sensory in character, but the seeming had only by the expert is itself not sensory. (For further examples, see the opening of Tucker 2010).
The seeming might even be sharable in principle with subjects who lack visual consciousness altogether (Tucker 2010, also Lyons 2005 with different terminology, Brogaard 2013 however disagrees that visual seemings can be detached so far from visual sensation). That seemings are not sensory does not obviously entail that they are perceptually amodal entirely, Lyons for instance seems to tie down his “nonexperiential looks” to different perceptual modalities such as vision or audition.
The example of the novice vs. the expert is suggestive, but what we have said so far leaves open the respective natures of sensations and seemings, as well as of how visual experiences are to be understood in relation to them. Given all of this indeterminacy, as well as the room for debate about whether we even have good reason to complicate the structure of visual experience in this way (see Chudnoff and Didomenico 2015 for criticisms), the discussion below will be framed simply in terms of visual experiences. That said, the discussion should remain applicable to experiences understood as combinations of some sort of sensations and seemings. The discussion should also in principle be adaptable to apply individually to sensations only or to seemings only, depending on the reader’s preferred category. At some key stages we will explicitly highlight where the distinction might be especially useful to apply and explore.
On sense-datum theories, whenever you have a visual experience as if there is something present that is red, there really is something present that is red—a sense-datum. Now, in many cases of illusions and hallucination, there won’t be any ordinary red thing around for you to experience even if there seems to you to be a red thing present. So sense-data are either going to be mental objects or strange non-mental objects. Sense-datum theories usually depart from the following principle:
The Phenomenal Principle
Whenever you visually experience it to be that case that something is \(F\), then there is something \(F\) that you experience (Robinson 1994).
Let’s first examine an epistemological case for sense-datum theories. Here the direction of flow is from epistemology to the philosophy of mind. We can find it in the following famous quote from H.H. Price:
When I see a tomato there is much that I can doubt … One thing however I cannot doubt: that there exists a red patch of a round and somewhat bulgy shape, standing out from a background of other colour-patches, and having a certain visual depth, and that this whole field of colour is presented to my consciousness … (Price 1932: 3).
On Price’s line of thought, perceptual experiences do afford us with some certainty. When Price sees a tomato, he may be certain that there is something red and round present. According to critics of the argument, Price is not entitled to be certain of any such thing. For example, his experience might merely represent that there exists something red and round present, where such representation can occur even if nothing red and round is present (for more on this objection see the entry on the problem of perception (section 3.1.2).
Let’s now turn to the status of beliefs about ordinary objects in the external world, and the flow from the philosophy of mind to epistemology. We can organize our discussion under the following instance of the trio:
Epistemology
Experiences justify beliefs about the external world.
Epistemology-Mind Link 1
If experiences justify beliefs about the external world, then experiences are not relations to sense-data.
Mind 1
Experiences are relations to sense-data.
In principle, a sense-datum theorist might accept E-M Link 1 and Mind 1, and conclude that Epistemology is false. For example, she might take up a coherence theory of justification, on which our beliefs about the external world are justified by their coherence with each other and not by experiences (see the entry on sense-data (section 3.2).
In the usual line of discussion, philosophers affirm Epistemology and E-M Link 1, and conclude that Mind 1 is false (see Berkeley 1710/2008: sect 18 or Reid 1764/1997: ch. 1). Sense-datum theories tell us that the things we are directly aware of in perceptual experience are not ordinary external objects. As the common metaphor has it, sense-data theories draw a veil of ideas over the world. The usual objection holds that this veil makes it impossible for us to gain knowledge or justified belief from experience about the external world. Philosophers such as Berkeley and Reid reject sense-datum theories on the grounds that we do have epistemic access to the world.
In response, the sense-datum theorist might deny E-M Link 1. In particular, the theorist might say that experiences justify beliefs about the external world when complemented with reflection on how they are best explained (Russell 1912). Call this the IBE approach since it concerns Inferences to the Best Explanation of our experiences (see Vogel 1990 for more contemporary discussion). Setting aside debate about how such an explanation might go, and why it might be the best, the response might not go far enough.
To see why the IBE approach might not go far enough, consider the idea that experiences provide non-inferential justification for beliefs about the external world. If experiences provide non-inferential justification for beliefs about the external world, they justify beliefs through a route that does not involve further beliefs. Compare how your sharp pain might justify you directly in believing that you are in pain, without further beliefs playing any role. Contrast how your thermometer might justify you in believing you have a fever only in conjunction with your having reason to believe the thermometer works. Non-inferential justification is justification that does not involve auxiliary beliefs (see Pryor 2005 for more detail).
On the IBE approach, it seems that experiences at best give us inferential justification for beliefs about the external world. That’s because they justify us only in conjunction with whatever beliefs their best explanation brings in. Experiences arguably do better (Johnston 2006). The veil of ideas objection might then be better put as follows:
Epistemology1
Experiences give non-inferential justification for beliefs about the external world.
Epistemology-Mind Link 2
If experiences give non-inferential justification for beliefs about the external world, then experiences are not relations to sense-data.
not-Mind 1
Experiences are not relations to sense-data.
Even still, it is unclear why sense-datum theories should rule out getting non-inferential justification from experiences. Perhaps if a sense-datum theory is true, we at best see external objects indirectly, by means of seeing sense-data. But this is only a point about seeing. Our justification for beliefs could still be non-inferential (Moore 1953; Silins 2011). The crucial question for non-inferential justification is about the role of background beliefs, and the mental process of indirect perception need not make use of background beliefs. For instance, whether you indirectly perceive objects by means of sense-data might instead just be a matter of how the sense-data are caused, leaving open the possibility that you gain non-inferential justification for beliefs about the external world from sense-data.
Let’s now zoom out to a big picture assessment of the epistemic implications of sense-datum theories.
The thought driving the veil of ideas worry is that if experiences fail to put us in direct contact with reality, then they cannot justify beliefs about external reality. This thought is meant to get us to the conclusion that sense datum theory is false. But it might go too far.
The first ramification concerns seeing objects. According to many views, we see ordinary extended objects by seeing their surfaces, rather than seeing them directly (see Moore 1918 or Broad 1952, and Clarke 1965 or Campbell 2004 for dispute). As far as seeing objects goes, their facing surfaces play the same role as sense-data did on many versions of the sense-datum theory—intermediaries not identical with objects that still permit us to see objects by seeing them. But now, if we endorse the veil of ideas objection, there is a risk that the facing surfaces of objects will be a veil over the rest of external reality. Call this the veil of surfaces. Our experiences might fail to give us access to whether we live in a world of ever shifting facades or instead a world of three-dimensional objects as they are ordinarily conceived. Descartes arguably states this problem when he writes:
I remember that, when looking from a window and saying I see men who pass in the street, I really do not see them, but infer that what I see is men, just as I say that I see wax. And yet what do I see from the window but hats and coats which may cover automatic machines? (PW, p. 21 )
If the veil of ideas objection succeeds against sense-data theories, it might also rule out the theory that we directly perceive only surfaces. It is not clear whether the objection can get us that far.
The veil of ideas objection also has controversial ramifications for cases of illusion or hallucination. When something looks red to you when it isn’t, or when you have a hallucination of a bloody dagger in front of you, your experience fails to put you in direct contact with reality as it is. According to many approaches, your experience might still—misleadingly—justify you in believing that reality is the way it visually appears to be. However, if the thought driving the veil of ideas objection is correct, experiences only justify in those cases when you are seeing things as they are. This is quite a demanding view, one that rules out justification in a wide range of cases where many think it is present. (For more discussion of views that exclude perceptual justification from cases of illusion or hallucination, see section 2.2.).
According to sense-data theories, all visual experiences relate us to objects with the properties attributed by our visual experiences. At an opposite extreme, one might hold that experiences are “raw feels”, failing to present the world to us in any way. To get a feel for this line of thought, consider the experience of “seeing stars”. According to some views, your experience here is a mere sensation, failing to present your surroundings to you (cf. Smith 2002: 130–1). On these views, the expression of “seeing stars” is extremely misleading here, as you do not literally see stars, and do not even figuratively see anything else—it is not as if your experience is of anything in the scene. According to raw feel theory, all visual experiences are in fact like this, not just exceptional ones. As Bonjour puts it, we capture what our visual experiences are like “in terms of patches of color arranged in two-dimensional visual space” (2001: 32). (For a survey of views that could fall under the heading of “raw feel theory” as used here, see entry on contents of perception (section 2.1).
In a passage from “A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge”, Donald Davidson can be read as using raw feel theory to argue for a skeptical epistemological conclusion:
The relation between a sensation and a belief cannot be logical, since sensations are not beliefs or other propositional attitudes. What then is the relation? The answer is, I think, obvious: the relation is causal. Sensations cause some beliefs and in this sense are the basis or ground of those beliefs. But a causal explanation of a belief does not show how or why the belief is justified. (1986: 310)
By itself, the view that experiences are raw feels is silent about whether experiences are able to justify beliefs about the external world. To get to conclusions about epistemology, some sort of linking principle is needed. Davidson’s idea is that a source can supply justification only if it has propositional content, so that the source is assessable as accurate or inaccurate, depending on whether the relevant proposition is true. On this way of setting up the issues, an experience has “propositional content” by having content that is assessable for truth (for further elaboration of the idea that experiences have propositional content, see the entry on the contents of perception). Given Davidson’s demand, experiences would be unable to justify beliefs if they were merely raw feels or sensations. (For important precedents to Davidson here, see Sellars 1956 and Popper 1959: chapter 5. For further contemporary discussion, see Bonjour 1985; McDowell 1994; Brewer 1999; and Pryor 2005.).
We can sketch the issues raised by Davidson with the following instance of our trio:
Epistemology
Experiences justify beliefs about the external world.
Epistemology-Mind Link 3
If experiences justify beliefs about the external world, then experiences have propositional content.
Mind 2
Experiences are raw feels without propositional content.
The Davidsonian response to the trio is to accept E-M Link 3 and Mind 2, but to deny Epistemology.
A different response to the trio accepts E-M Link3, but uses Epistemology to reject Mind 2. This position was occupied by McDowell 1994 and Brewer 1999 (although they later revised their views in Brewer 2006 and McDowell 2009).
Let us focus on debate about E-M Link 3, the common ground between Davidson, McDowell and Brewer. It can be resisted by raw feel theorists, as well as by non-raw feel theorists who fall short of attributing propositional contents to experiences.
Why believe E-M Link 3 at all? Davidson’s own case appeals to the claim that, in order for an experience to justify a belief, the experience must make more probable or entail the content of the belief (he also uses the further assumption that only propositional contents can do any such thing). It’s not clear why all raw feel theorists must accept the demand. Think back to the experience of “seeing stars”, and suppose that the experience is indeed a raw feel. The experience might still justify the belief that you are having that particular experience. Analogously, if pains are best understood as raw feels, they arguably could still justify you in believing that you have them. Now, if experiences could lack propositional contents and still justify you in believing you have them, why couldn’t they still also justify beliefs about the external world? In particular, at least if background beliefs are allowed to play a role, it seems perfectly possible for beliefs about the external world to be justified thanks to the availability of inferences linking particular raw feels with particular conditions of the external world. The justificatory structure here would look like this:
(For a contemporary view with this sort of structure, see Bonjour 2001).
One also might try to meet the spirit of the demand that justifiers increase probability or entail without attributing propositional contents to experiences. Here it’s important to note the rich range of ways in which experiences might be directed at the world. Many of these ways need not involve propositional content.
First, even if experiences lack contents that are assessable for truth, experiences might still have contents that are assessable for accuracy. Burge 2010 suggests that experiences have non-propositional contents of the form ‘that \(F\)’, and are accurate just in case the referent has the property \(F\). Alternatively, consider how a map or picture might be accurate or inaccurate without being true or false. When experiences are accurate in either of these ways, other contents of beliefs will be true. So experiences could lack propositional contents, but still count as close enough to entailing the contents of beliefs or to increasing the probability of the contents of beliefs.
Second, experiences might lack contents altogether, and not be assessable for truth or accuracy, but still be related in important ways to relations to the world such as seeing (Campbell 2002; McDowell 2009; Brewer 2006, 2011). According to these approaches that resist the ascription of content to experiences, your experience justifies a belief about the world only when your experience is a case of seeing the world as it is. You can see the world as it is only if it is in fact that way. Here many of your experiences might be supremely positioned to justify whether or not they have any content. (For more about such approaches, see subsection 2.2.).
In sum, raw feel theorists might be in a good position to reject E-M Link 3. Moreover, even if experiences are not raw feels, they might also lack propositional contents, and still be directed at the world in a way that helps them to justify beliefs.
Let us now turn to more fine-grained connections between contents of experience and perceptual justification, focusing on contents of experience that can be assessed for truth.
First, is having specifically the content that \(p\) necessary for an experience to justify believing that \(p\)? Here is a first pass at capturing the issue:
Epistemology-Mind Link4
If your visual experience \(e\) gives you justification to believe some external world proposition that \(p\), then \(e\) has the content that \(p\).
A challenge comes from cases when you use an experience and background beliefs to extrapolate far beyond any content the experience might have. For example, when I have an experience in New York with the content that the traffic light is red, my background beliefs enable the experience to justify me in believing that cars might still be permitted to turn right. But this legally informed belief is in a content that most likely does not figure in my experience.
To accommodate extrapolation beyond experience thanks to auxiliary beliefs, the simplest response is to focus on non-inferential justification that does not involve auxiliary beliefs.
Epistemology-Mind Link5
If your visual experience \(e\) gives you non-inferential justification to believe some external world proposition that \(p\), then \(e\) has the content that \(p\).
If Link5 is true, it allows for rich connections between theories of perceptual experience and theories of perceptual justification. Consider for instance the debate about “high-level” content. Very roughly, this debate is about whether our experiences merely represent colors, shapes and locations, or whether they represent thicker properties or relations such as causing an explosion, being a fake Louis Vuitton bag, being virtuous, or being glad to see you (for more see the entry on the contents of perception). If Link5 is true, and we have non-inferential justification for belief in high-level contents, it will follow that some of our experiences have high-level contents as well. But how to establish that our experiences give us non-inferential justification for some high-level beliefs?
One route is to try to leverage the psychological immediacy of our formation of some high-level beliefs. When the fashionista sees the droopy bag marked “Louis Vuitton” in a cheap Shenzhen mall, she does not need to pull out her lighter to test whether the material melts likes plastic. Instead she forms her belief that the bag is a fake Louis Vuitton without any conscious reflection. Likewise, we don’t need to puzzle out whether our loved ones are present when we see them—we seem to recognize them on the basis of our experiences without reasoning. Still, it may be that auxiliary beliefs are playing a role in all these examples while remaining unconscious. The psychological immediacy of belief formation needn’t go along with non-inferential justification (see McDowell 1982).
For further discussion of how to show we have non-inferential justification from experiences for some beliefs in high-level contents, and of whether the experiences themselves would need to have high-level contents to do so, see Millar 2000, McDowell 2009, or Silins 2013.
For further defense of the claim that an experience justifies a belief only if it has a content identical with that of the belief, see McDowell 1994 and Brewer 1999. For critical responses, see Speaks 2005 and Byrne 2005.
Is having the content that \(p\) enough for an experience to justifying you believing that \(p\)? Here is a first pass at capturing the idea:
Sufficiency First Pass
If you have an experience \(e\) with the content that \(p\), then \(e\) gives you justification to believe that \(p\).
The Sufficiency thesis is not formulated in terms of non-inferential justification. For all it says, whenever an experience justifies a belief, it does so only in a way involving the assistance of an auxiliary belief. Still, the picture does mesh well with views on which experiences give non-inferential justification, and we may understand it in those terms in what follows.
Our thesis does need to be qualified. For example, suppose that you gain convincing evidence that you are the victim of an illusion, as when you learn that the lines of the Müller-Lyer illusion are the same in length even though they look to be different in length:
Figure 1. Müller-Lyer illusion [1]
Your experience does not give you justification to believe that the lines are different in length once you have gain the evidence they are the same in length. Such cases are ones of “defeat”, where further evidence opposes or otherwise disrupts your receipt of justification from your experience (some cases may be like someone writing over the graffiti drawn by experience, other cases may be like someone erasing the graffiti drawn by experience, and perhaps there are further variants of defeat as well). To take account of such cases, the fan of Sufficiency can say that
Sufficiency
If you have an experience \(e\) with the content that \(p\), then \(e\) gives you defeasible justification to believe that \(p\).
Here the core idea is that your experience gives you justification unless you have gained evidence that your experience is misleading.
For defenses of theses along the lines of Sufficiency, see Pollock (1974), Pryor (2000) or Huemer (2001, 2007). Their strategies put much weight on what it is like to have an experience (see more in section 2.4 on this sort of strategy). A different approach tries to exploit the way that experiences come to have their contents, for example by arguing that experiences are likely to have true or accurate contents given the way they come to have their contents. For examples of this strategy, see Burge 2003, Peacocke 2004, Sawyer and Majors 2005, and Setiya 2012: ch. 3.
The Sufficiency thesis also promises to establish rich connections between epistemology and the philosophy of mind. Consider again the debate about high-level contents of experience. If one is able to establish that experiences have high-level contents, one could then use the Sufficiency thesis to reach the conclusion that experiences justify beliefs in high-level contents as well.
Assuming that experiences with the content that \(p\) will give non-inferential justification for a belief that \(p\), we could then have an answer to an important question for foundationalist views in epistemology. These are views on which our inferentially justified beliefs about the external world are inferred from a foundation of non-inferentially justified beliefs (for more see the entry on foundationalist theories of epistemic justification). Which beliefs get to be in the foundation? This question for foundationalist views is pressing. As Nozick remarks, it is of little use to have a foundation for our knowledge that is only one brick wide (1981: 3). In general, the more restrictive foundationalist views are about the breadth of our foundational beliefs, the harder it will be to build up to everyday beliefs about the world. However, if beliefs concerning causation, emotions, or morality get to be foundational, the foundationalist project can look much more promising (Masrour 2011).
As helpful as the Sufficiency thesis could be for foundationalists, it faces much criticism. Many objections proceed by proposing requirements for justification that are not always satisfied when one has an experience with a given content. For example, one might demand that the experience be a case of seeing (section 2.2 of this entry), or demand that the experience be suitably free of top-down influence from one’s own mind (section 2.4 of this entry). (For further objections, see McGrath 2017 or Chudnoff 2018).
Here we will focus on objections that turn on the character of perceptual content. The objection here is known as “the problem of the speckled hen” (see Chisholm 1942; Sosa in Sosa and Bonjour 2003; Markie 2009 for different versions of the problem).
To get a feel for our problem, suppose you get a look at a speckled hen in good light, but without enough time to carefully count the number of speckles on it.
Figure 2. “Speckled Sussex Hen named Mata Hari” [2]
The objection to Sufficiency can be put as follows. First, your experience does have a verdict about how many spots face you—say to the effect that \(H\) has 17 spots. Second, your experience does not justify you in believing that \(H\) has 17 spots. After all, forming a belief that \(H\) has 17 spots without carefully counting might manifestly seem no more likely to be right than a guess. So, the critic concludes, some experiences have the content that \(p\) without giving you justification to believe that \(p\).
In response, some argue that your experience is actually silent about the exact number of speckles facing you on the hen (see Tye 2009; for more on experience and numeracy, see Beck 2012).
One can raise the core challenge to Sufficiency in other ways. Another source of examples can be found in Block’s (2007) empirically informed work on “phenomenal overflow” (drawing on Sperling 1960 and Lamme 2003). Consider for example the Sperling paradigm, in which subjects are flashed a grid of letters, and only subsequently given a tone that indicates which row to report (high for the top, medium for the middle, etc). Subjects are able to report any row singled out without being able to report them all. (For an online demo without sound, see Other Internet Resources). Arguably subjects experience all the letters as they are without being able to report them all (but see Stazicker 2011 or Phillips 2011 for criticisms of Block, also Odegaard et al 2018). The objector may add that we do not have justification from our experience to believe the proposition that enumerates all the letters present. (For a further way to set up the speckled hen problem, using the example of highly determinate colors, see Smithies 2019: ch. 11).
Even if one allows that some experiences have enough determinacy to set up the speckled hen problem, the option remains of maintaining that the experiences do give you justification to believe the relevant determinate proposition. For example, perhaps your experiences do give you justification to believe the determinate proposition, even though you are unable to take advantage of the justification you have by forming a belief on their basis (see Smithies 2012a for a view with this structure).
Alternatively, perhaps speckled hen cases are compatible with Sufficiency since they turn out to be cases of defeat. Given that we are generally aware of our poor ability to make snap judgments about the details of the scene before, perhaps we have defeasible but defeated justification to believe detailed propositions about the scene before us.
So far we have focused on the ramifications for epistemology of the view that experiences have propositional contents. Intentionalism is a more ambitious view in the philosophy of mind that aims to find necessary connections between the conscious character of an experience—what it is like to have it—and the content of that experience. According to intentionalists, at a minimum,
Minimal Intentionalism
If experiences \(e_1\) and \(e_2\) have the same content, then what it is like to have \(e_1\) is the same as what it is like to have \(e_2\).
In a slogan, “same content, same character” (for discussion of further variations in the camp, see Chalmers 2004). On this picture, if two experiences present the same testimony about the world, there is no room for any difference in what it is like to have those experiences. Whether there is such a tight link between content and conscious character is controversial, consider the frequently discussed possibility that your shifting attention could vary the conscious character of two distinct experiences without varying their testimony about the world.
Here we will point to some epistemological ramifications of the view.
One way to defend Intentionalism examines how we become introspectively aware of what it’s like to have our experiences. Arguably we become introspectively aware of what it’s like to have our experiences only by being aware of what we are experiencing. Perhaps awareness of the world is the sole route to introspective awareness of what it’s like to have a given experience. And perhaps this point about introspection supports at least a minimal version of Intentionalism. For further discussion of this broadly epistemological argument for intentionalism, see the entry on qualia (section 6), also the entry on representational theories of consciousness (section 3.3).
Another defense of Intentionalism examines how we become able to think about certain properties by having experiences. Perhaps experiences are sufficient for certain cognitive abilities, and perhaps Intentionalism gives the best explanation of how experiences are sufficient for certain cognitive abilities. For an exposition of this broadly epistemological line of argument for Intentionalism, see Pautz 2010.
For an epistemological argument against some versions of Intentionalism, see Kriegel 2011. He targets versions of the view that aim to find what constitutes experience in terms of awareness of properties (or a suitably similar relation to properties). According to Kriegel, just as sense-data theories are unable to provide an adequate epistemology because of the “veil of appearances” they impose between perceivers and the world, the targeted versions of Intentionalism fail to provide an adequate epistemology for the same reason. As we saw in section 2.1, sense-data theorists have ways to respond to veil objections. Perhaps intentionalists do as well.
An uncontroversial theory of perceptual experiences holds that they all have a conscious character—for any experience \(e\) there is something it is like to have \(e\). Further, part of what it is for something to be an experience is for it to have a conscious character. There is much debate about how to explain the nature of perceptual consciousness, but there is little debate about whether something is an experience only if it has a conscious character.
There is much more room for debate about the importance of consciousness for the epistemology of perception. One strategy of explaining how experiences justify beliefs focuses on their conscious character. We may call it the phenomenal approach.
To see why this approach is a contender, consider subjects who have “blindsight”. They have visual representations of what’s in their blind field without having conscious visual experience of anything in their blind field (see Weiskrantz 2009 for a survey, and Phillips and Block 2016 for a debate about whether there really is unconscious perception). Now these subjects are better than chance at identifying objects in their blind field, but they have to be prompted to make a guess. For our purposes, imagine a hypothetical blindsighted subject who does not need to be prompted to form a belief that there is an \(X\) to the left. Now compare that subject with an ordinary sighted subject who forms a belief that there is an \(X\) to the left on the basis of visual experience. There are various questions here whose answers might support the phenomenal approach (see Smithies 2012a, 2019: ch. 3 for more).
First, is the blindsighted subject completely unjustified in believing that there is an \(X\) to the left? If you think the answer to this question is yes, and you’re not a skeptic about the sighted subject, you arguably should be sympathetic to the phenomenal approach. What else would explain this difference between them?
Second, is the blindsighted subject at any rate less justified than the sighted subject in believing that there is an \(X\) to the left? If you think the answer here is yes, again you arguably should be sympathetic to the phenomenal approach. What else would explain this epistemic difference between them?
In response, one might deny that the epistemic differences obtain (see Lyons 2009, also Berger 2020). Even if one accepts that the epistemic differences obtain, one might still insist that they are equally or better explained by alternative candidates than consciousness. For example, perhaps the blindsighted subject does not count as seeing the \(X\), and perhaps the sighted subject is more justified than the blindsighted subject simply thanks to seeing the \(X\) (as an \(X\)). Here the explanatory burden would be borne by bearing a perceptual relation to the thing, rather than having an experience with a certain character.
Here it might help to compare the sighted subject with a conscious subject for whom things are just the same from the inside, but who fails to see any \(X\) because she is hallucinating. If the sighted subject and the hallucinating subject are equally justified in believing there is an \(X\) to the left, visual experience might be a better candidate than seeing to explain the epistemic symmetry between the sighted and the hallucinating subjects.
Suppose the blindsighted subject and sighted subject are equally justified—is the phenomenal approach then doomed? Speaking loosely, even if the blindsighted subject has the same epistemic effect as the sighted subject, it’s not entirely clear that there must be the same cause (or perhaps there is a common unconscious cause present even in the sighted subject).
To support the claim that consciousness doesn’t supply perceptual justification, one might look to other real-life cases of unconscious visual representation. One sort of case is that of unconscious priming. Here you are exposed to a stimulus too quickly for it to register in visual experience, but for all that it still does affect your behavior. For example, an unconsciously registered numeral might improve your ability to report that a subsequently seen numeral is greater or lower than 5, depending on whether the priming one is itself greater or lower than 5 (Naccache and Dehaene 2001). Now this sort of case is arguably not one in which unconscious visual representations justify. The subjects concerned plausibly do not form beliefs that are good candidates to be justified by their unconscious visual representations. But consider people with visual hemi-neglect, who seem to lack conscious visual experience of their neglected field.
Some neglect patients seem to take in information about the neglected stimuli, and to form beliefs about it. For instance, some of them, when presented with a burning house in their neglected field and a normal house in their normal field, prefer the one that isn’t on fire (Marshall and Halligan 1988; Bisiach and Rusconi 1990). Here they do form a belief that is a candidate to be justified by their unconscious visual representation. Their belief that the house in their neglected field isn’t preferable might be justified by the information they take in, even if the intake is through unconscious perception. If this case is one in which the subject is justified, and justified to the same degree as in ordinary cases of conscious perception, one might then start to wonder whether consciousness must play a role even in ordinary cases of perceptual justification. Perhaps it is side-stepped by unconscious visual representations even then.
If the conscious character of experiences does play a justifying role, a further question remains about why it does so. One might hold that there is no further explanation to be provided here. Perhaps the capacity of consciousness to justify is a fundamental fact of epistemology. According to another proposal, consciousness justifies thanks to being introspectively accessible. On this internalist conception of justification, a special kind of access to a source is necessary for the source to provide justification, and consciousness stands out for allowing this sort of access (see e.g. Smithies 2012b, 2019).
Here we will focus on a particular aspect of the conscious character of experiences, one highlighted by Pryor (2000) among others. To get a feel for this feature if you are sighted, first look away from this surface and imagine a black circle in front of you. Now look at this surface and have a visual experience of the black circle in front of you constituting the period ending this sentence.
In the former case, you were not justified in believing that there is a black circle in front of you. In the present case, you are. One candidate way to explain the epistemic difference is to focus on a difference between what it is like to imagine and what it is like to have a visual experience (see Martin 2002 for more).
The salient feature of experience here is not easy to pin down. The rough idea is that, when you visually experience, as opposed to when you visually imagine, things are presented to you as actually being the case. How this feature of experience is best to be understood is open to debate. For now let us leave open its exact nature and simply use the term “presentational phenomenology” as a place-holder for whatever it is (for more elaboration see Chudnoff 2012 or Bengson 2015, and see Teng 2018 for a challenge to privileging presentational phenomenology).
Even if presentational phenomenology is epistemically privileged, there remains an important question about its scope. Suppose you see a cow through a picket fence. There is arguably some way you perceptually “get” that there is an extended cow there. For a dramatic contrast, start by considering Damien Hirst’s Some Comfort Gained From the Acceptance of the Inherent Lies in Everything, that consists of a cow vertically sliced into a series of boxes arranged like dominos. Now suppose you know you are seeing the Hirst sculpture through a picket fence, where the segments align exactly with the gaps in the fence. Here you arguably would not perceptually “get” that there is an elongated cow there.
In the ordinary case of seeing a cow through a picket fence, it is debatable whether presentational phenomenology includes the presence of an extended cow, or whether it includes only those regions of the cow not occluded by the fence (see Noe 2005 for further discussion). If your presentational phenomenology includes only the non-occluded regions, and only presentational phenomenology supplies perceptual justification, the rational powers of experience threaten to be limited. You would not have justification to believe that an extended cow is present just by taking your experience of the cow through the slats at face value. Analogously, if only the facing surface of an object is phenomenally present, you might have justification to believe only that the facing surface is present by taking your experience at face value. Here we might find ourselves back at the “veil of surfaces” discussed in section 2.2.
Some might accept this prediction. In his 2018a and 2018b, Chudnoff in effect does. He compares seeing an ordinary occluded dog with seeing an unfamiliar occluded blob, and claims that our visual experience in such cases has presentational phenomenology only with respect to what is not occluded, and gives us immediate justification for beliefs with respect to only what is not occluded. On his view, our background information about dogs picks up the slack to enable us to have a justified belief about the full shape of the dog, whereas no background information is available for us to have a justified belief about the full shape of the occluded blob. In response, Helton and Nanay 2018 in effect argue that Chudnoff’s view threatens to lead to skepticism about ordinary beliefs about occluded objects, and underestimates the powers of visual experience with respect to novel occluded objects. To avoid potential skeptical problems, some may prefer to take a more expansive view of presentational phenomenology.
We have spoken so far about experiences justifying beliefs in an all or nothing way. As Munton 2016 reminds us, visual experiences can justify the same belief to differing degrees. For example, suppose you are looking outside at the park on a foggy and snowy morning, and gradually get a better view of a new snowman as the fog clears. Here your successive visual experiences of the snowman justify your belief that there is a snowman in the park more and more as the fog clears. Perceptual justification comes in degrees.
A caution about how to set up the issue is in order. If you think that perceptual justification is only binary and does not come in degrees, you should avoid the following common formulation of that sort of view: either your experience justifies a belief that there is a snowman in the park or it does not. We can all agree that the law of excluded middle applies to perceptual justification, that doesn’t yet rule out the possibility that perceptual justification comes in degrees. For example, perhaps your experience justifies a belief when the degree of justification it gives is sufficiently high, and otherwise not. This is a scenario in which your experience either justifies a belief or it does not, as well as a scenario where perceptual justification comes in degrees.
According to Munton, we can now draw a conclusion about the nature of visual experiences, in effect using the template we have surveyed so far (I focus on Munton’s argument because she puts epistemology front and center. A related argument by Morrison 2016 instead focuses on variations in what happens when we form opinions by completely trusting our experiences, but this argument departs from psychology rather than epistemology).
As a first pass we can try the following:
Epistemology2
Our experiences justify beliefs about the external world to varying degrees.
Epistemology-Mind Link6
If our experiences justify beliefs about the external world to varying degrees, then our experiences are themselves degreed.
Mind3
Our experiences are themselves degreed.
The conclusion that experiences are degreed is striking and important, but it can be elaborated in quite different ways.
One choice point is where to locate potential variation in degrees. One option would be in the contents of the experiences, another would be in the mental relation we bear to contents or to the world in having an experience (variation in principle could be located in the vehicles of experiences as well or somewhere else). A further choice point is about how to understand variations in degrees of experiences. A tempting option is to piggyback on probabilistic theorizing about credences or degrees of belief (but bear in mind that in principle experiences could be degreed without being degreed in a probabilistic way). The idea here is to cash out the idea that experiences are degreed in a similar way to how philosophers cash out the idea that credences are degreed (without necessarily saying that experiences simply are credences). So just as you might have a higher credence that the 4-sided die will land 4 than the 6-sided die might land 4, perhaps you also have a higher visual credence that there is a snowman out there when the fog is lighter, as opposed to when the fog is heavier. Now, how to understand credences themselves is open to dispute, where again dimensions of variation might be located in differing mental relations to the content that the die will land 4, or potentially instead in different contents concerning 1/6 probabilities as opposed to 1/6 probabilities. Also, even if credences are themselves best understood in probabilistic terms, that is not yet to say that credences are best understood specifically in Bayesian terms. So degreed views of experience aren’t forced to commit specifically to Bayesian views of perception (for more on probabilistic views of perception, often focusing more on the processes leading to perception rather than what is generated by those processes, see Hohwy 2013, Rescorla 2015, Siegel 2020, or Vance 2021). Understanding degreed experiences along the lines of credences opens a wide menu of options.
For a final complication, note that there is extensive debate about the relation between traditionally conceived beliefs and credences. One eliminativist option ultimately denies that there are beliefs, replacing them with credences. Other approaches keep both beliefs and credences in the picture, and understand beliefs in terms of credences, or credences in terms of belief, or neither in terms of the other (see section 4 of SEP entry on formal representations of belief). Likewise, once one has admitted experiences that are degreed somehow in the manner of credences, one might at the same time still allow for other experiences more like traditionally understood beliefs. So there is now room for the questions about the relation between beliefs and credences to play out in the case of experiences that are structured along the lines of beliefs vs. degreed experiences structured along the lines of credences. Perhaps there only are degreed experiences structured like credences, or perhaps there are also experiences structured like beliefs, where we can ask whether either of the two entities has explanatory priority in relation to the other.
In sum, understanding experiences as being degreed in the manner of credences is a fascinating line of research, but also a multi-pronged one given the extent range of questions about credences.
Now that we’ve seen some of the possibilities that arise if experiences are degreed, the question remains of whether the epistemic argument above establishes that any of them is actual.
In order to make the needed link from epistemology to mind plausible, the linking premise and the rest of the argument need to be refined right away. The strategy is to trace variation of degrees in justification to variations of degrees in experience, but rival candidates for explaining the variation need to be blocked. For all we have said so far, the variation in degrees of justification could be traced not to experiences, but rather to differing degrees of justification to believe that your experiences are trustworthy (depending on the conditions of fog).
To block a role for differences in your background beliefs, Munton in effect focuses on immediate justification for your experiences (using the terminology of “direct” justification). This gives us the following
Epistemology3
Our experiences immediately justify beliefs about the external world to varying degrees.
Epistemology-Mind Link6
If our experiences immediately justify beliefs about the external world to varying degrees, then our experiences are themselves degreed.
Mind3
Our experiences are themselves degreed.
Even given these refinements, rival explanations still need to be blocked. For example, perhaps the new version of Epistemology is false, and experiences only provide specifically immediate justification in optimal cases (for discussion see Munton 2016). Or perhaps the new version of Link is false, and the variations in degrees of justification can be explained in line with a traditional non-degreed picture of what experiences are. For example, consider that your experience plausibly concerns not just the potential snowman in the park, but also the amount of fog in the park and other aspects of your viewing conditions. And consider the phenomenon of defeat, where information you receive can reduce or destroy the amount of justification given by your experience. Given that your experience in effect takes a stand on the quality of your viewing conditions, perhaps your experiences in higher conditions of fog undermine the degree of justification they supply specifically to believe a snowman is there. Here we might explain the variation of degrees of justification through variation in the experience, but through garden variety non-degreed perceptual content concerning viewing conditions, rather than any more striking degreed character of the experiences (this sort of objection is discussed further in Beck 2020).
We have now surveyed the epistemic implications of some central theories of experience. We have by no means covered all theories of experience. Here we will simply point to further important areas to consider. For discussion of naïve realist theories of experience, and of their interaction with issues about skepticism, see the entries on epistemological problems of perception and the disjunctive theory of perception. For discussion of how dualist theories of experience might lead to epiphenomenalism, where epiphenomenalism might lead to skeptical problems, see the entry on epiphenomenalism (section 2.3). For discussion of the theory that experience is actually a special case of belief, where that theory might affect our understanding of how we base beliefs on experiences, see the entry on the contents of perception (section 2.2).
Let us now consider the significance for epistemology of a range of perceptual phenomena. On most views, these phenomena do not occur in all cases of perception, but still have important ramifications for the epistemology of perception.
The first array of phenomena are concerned with the relation between experience and the world. Here we will consider different kinds of perceptual error, as well as forms of perception that occur only in the absence of error. The remaining phenomena we will consider are characterized by the internal etiology of experience. Here we will look at the influence of attention and of other mental states on our experience.
In cases of perceptual error, we form a false belief on the basis of a misleading experience, as when an uninformed subject concludes there is motion below (to get the effect, let your eyes drift over the image):
Figure 3. “Rotating snakes” [3]
This is a paradigm case of an illusion, where you do see a scene, but misperceive what the scene is like. In a paradigm case of hallucination, you have a perceptual experience, but do not perceive anything in the scene before you.
Few dispute that there are cases of perceptual error (although some disagree about whether perceptual error is ever properly at the level of experience as opposed to that of beliefs formed on the basis of experiences, cf. Brewer 2006). Many skeptical arguments use the occurrence of perceptual error to conclude that experiences do not do a particular job in epistemology. We can understand these arguments as using different versions of the Epistemology-Mind Link:
Epistemology-Mind Link7
If experiences sometimes deceive us, then experiences do not give us knowledge of the external world.
Epistemology-Mind Link8
If experiences sometimes deceive us, then experiences do not give us justified beliefs about the external world.
For discussion of how to supplement or defend such principles, see the entries on skepticism and epistemological problems of perception.
Here we will focus on a weaker principle that addresses the kind of justification we can get from perceptual experiences:
Epistemology-Mind Link9
If experiences sometimes deceive us, then experiences at best give us inferential justification for beliefs about the external world.
If our experiences sometime deceive us, there is a “gap” between our having of the experience and the truth of the proposition they putatively justify. On E-M Link9, some intermediate belief will then be needed to close the gap between experience and truth, for example a belief to the effect that our experiences are reliable. Given the need for an intermediate belief, our experiences will then arguably fail to give us non-inferential justification for beliefs about the external world. This conclusion is endorsed by some philosophers who still reject skepticism about perceptual justification (Cohen 2002; Wright 2004; or White 2006).
E-M Link9 might still lead to skepticism. Consider an auxiliary belief meant to bridge the gap between experience and truth, and ask whether whatever process that lead to it might sometimes deceive us. For example, consider your belief that your experiences are reliable, and whatever process led to your belief that your experiences are reliable. That process could arguably lead you to falsely believe your experiences are reliable in a situation where you are radically deceived by an evil demon.
We now have a gap between the occurring of the process that led to an auxiliary belief and the truth of the auxiliary belief. So then, according to the reasoning behind E-M Link9, we would need another auxiliary belief to bridge the gap. Since an evil demon could presumably deceive us yet again, a threat of vicious regress arises here ((White 2006 articulates this line of thought without endorsing it (or explaining where it goes wrong)).
We have considered the significance of illusion and hallucination. Let’s now examine the case of dreams. Dreams are often understood to be paradigms of perceptual error, for example by Descartes when, discussing his apparent perceptions, he writes that
this would not happen with such distinctness to someone asleep. Indeed! As if I did not remember other occasions when I have been tricked by exactly similar thoughts while asleep! (PW, p. 13)
The picture of dreaming as a case of perceptual error is challenged by Sosa (2005).
We can frame the issue with a simplified argument for skepticism:
Epistemology-Mind Link10
If our experiences justify beliefs about our present surroundings, our experiences do not frequently deceive us while we dream.
Mind4
Our experiences frequently deceive us while we dream.
Not-Epistemology
Our experiences do not justify our beliefs about our present surroundings.
Sosa responds (to a more complex skeptical argument focused on knowledge) by defending an alternative conception of dreams known as “the imagination model”. According to the imagination model, we actually do not form beliefs about our surroundings when we dream, or even have perceptual experiences when we dream.
In defense of the imagination model, consider that, when I go to bed, I form and store a belief that I am lying in bed. If I were to form a belief while I am dreaming that I am running away from lions, I would then have a belief that contradicts my stored belief that I am lying in bed. Now we arguably do not have such contradictory beliefs while we are dreaming. The view that we form beliefs while dreaming might then be what has to go (Sosa 2005: 6).
Let’s now consider the case of visual experience. On the imagination model, when dreaming we do not even have visual experiences with the same conscious character as those we have when awake (we leave open whether we have “visual experiences” while dreaming in some extended sense). The argument at this stage can exploit the earlier conclusion that we do not form beliefs about our surroundings while dreaming. Sosa defends the further thesis on the grounds that, if we did have experiences when dreaming with the conscious character of those we have when awake, we would be open to epistemic criticism for failing to form beliefs that take our experiences at face value. However when I dream that I am being attacked by a lion, but do not believe while I dream that I am being attacked by a lion, I arguably am not open to epistemic criticism.
If the imagination model of dreaming is correct, the skeptical argument above is unsound because Mind is false. For discussion of whether Sosa succeeds in blocking the best dreaming arguments for skepticism, see Ichikawa 2009. For further discussion specifically of the visual character of dreams, see Schwitzgebel 2011: ch. 1.
Some epistemologists privilege perceptual states that you are in only if you are not in cases of illusion or hallucination. On their views, these states are either the only sources of perceptual justification, or at any rate the best sources of perceptual justification. In the terminology of Hawthorne and Kovakovich 2006, we may call these perceptual states “success states”.
To get a sense of some of the candidate states, consider the following table:
(Successful) vision | Illusion | Hallucination | |
---|---|---|---|
Having a visual experience with the content that \(a\) is \(F\) | Y | Y | Y |
Seeing \(a\) as being \(F\) | Y | Y | N |
Seeing that \(a\) is \(F\) | Y | N | N |
Seeing \(a\)’s \(F\)ness | Y | N | N |
(In setting up this table, we assume that hallucinations of a particular object are possible. For discussion, see Johnston 2004 or Schellenberg 2010.)
Epistemologists differ according to which success states they privilege, what job they assign to the state, and how severely they regard the absence of the privileged state.
For views which privilege seeing that \(p\), see McDowell (1982, 1995) or A. Jackson (2011). For views which privilege something along the lines of seeing \(a\)’s \(F\)ness, see Johnston (2006). These states are fact-entailing, since as a matter of necessity, you see that \(a\) is \(F\), or see \(a\)’s \(F\)ness, only if \(a\) is in fact \(F\). For a view that potentially favors the sort of perceptual state you find in cases of vision and illusion rather than hallucination, see Burge (2003). This sort of state is relational, since you can be in it only if the relevant object of perception is present in your scene. Assuming that each conscious success state has a counterpart in unconscious perception, notice that versions of these views might focus on perceptual states in common between conscious subjects and subjects without conscious perception.
In principle, you might get perceptual justification from a success state in the good case of vision or illusion, and get the same amount of perceptual justification from a non-success state in the bad case of hallucination (Lord forthcoming takes up a view with this structure regarding reasons for belief). We bracket that sort of approach here. It is more common to hold that you get no perceptual justification in the case of hallucination (e.g., Jackson 2011), or at least a lower degree or different kind of perceptual justification in the case of hallucination (e.g., Schellenberg 2013).
Let’s group views that privilege success states under the label “Success Theory”, and leave open how to adjudicate within the camp.
In support of Success Theory, one can emphasize the tight connection the approach draws between perceptual justification and truth. On many versions of the approach, the state that gives you justification to believe that \(a\) is \(F\) guarantees the truth of the belief that \(a\) is \(F\). Moreover, the source of your justification remains mental and arguably accessible to you, thus satisfying the demands of some “internalist” approaches in epistemology that privilege what is inside the subject or accessible in a special way by the subject (Prichard 2012). Moreover, Success Theory has a promising connection with issues about skepticism. They promise to block skeptical arguments that assume our evidence is the same between the good case of successful vision and the bad case of radical deception or hallucination (McDowell 1995, for a critique, see Wright 2004).
As an objection to Success Theory, many bring in demands on justification that are not satisfied by the most versions of the view. For instance, consider the internalist thesis that, if things seem the same to each of two people from the inside, then those two people are equally justified in their beliefs. More specifically, if two people have the same conscious perspective on the world, and the same stored beliefs, then they are the same with respect to the degree of justification of their beliefs. This sort of thesis is often motivated by considering radically deceived counterparts to us, and appealing to the intuition that such subjects and us are equally justified (Lehrer and Cohen 1983; Cohen 1984; Wedgwood 2002; for dispute, see Sutton 2007 or Littlejohn 2012). Now, if a version of Success Theory predicts that a subject in perceptual error has less justification than a corresponding perceiver, that version might be rejected on the basis of its conflict with the internalist thesis.
In response, one might attempt to explain away the intuition of equal justification as instead concerning equal blamelessness or excusability, or at any rate as being correct only if restricted to blamelessness or excusability (e.g. Williamson 2007 or forthcoming). Critics often try to respond by distinguishing the sort of blamelessness or excusability one finds in cases of cognitive delusion or brainwashing, from the epistemic status of the beliefs of the victim of an evil demon (Pryor 2001), or by demanding a more thorough explanation of why the victim is indeed blameless or excusable (Miracchi forthcoming). Recent literature also steps back to examine whether a substantive distinction can be drawn between justification and excusability, surveying potential distinctive explanatory roles for epistemic excuses to play (Greco 2019).
Alternatively, someone with a “disjunctive theory of perception” might insist that the radically deceived subject does not have the same conscious perspective on the world as the successful perceiver (Fish 2013, also the entry on the disjunctive theory of perception). On this line of thought, to have the conscious perspective of someone in a case of perceptual success, you need to be in a case of perceptual success. Here the antecedent of the internalist thesis is not satisfied in cases of radical deception. One challenge here is that there are many ways to be deceived. For example, when someone sees that a lemon is yellow, they might well lack a conscious counterpart who hallucinates, but they arguably still have a conscious counterpart who sees a fake lemon that is yellow. If the subject in a case of vision and the subject in a case of illusion are equally justified, that will be trouble for approaches that give justifying privilege to the states of seeing that \(a\) is \(F\) or seeing \(a\)’s \(F\)ness.
Some philosophers might attack Success Theory on the grounds that it is too internalist rather than not internalist enough. According to theorists such as Ginsborg 2006 or Roessler 2009, the justifiers of perceptual beliefs are best understood to be facts about the external world rather than facts about perceivers’ mind.
Standard cases of perceptual justification are ones in which you attend to what you see, as when you attend to your mail and form a justified belief that you have mail. But are all cases of perceptual justification ones in which attention is involved? According to the Attention Needed view, only attentive experiences can provide justification. According to the Attention Optional view, inattentive experiences can provide propositional justification.
If you only experience what you attend to, as is maintained by philosophers such as Prinz 2012, all cases of justification by experience will trivially involve attention as well. Here we’ll pursue the issue on the assumption that we sometimes experience something we do not attend to, as is held by theorists such as Searle 1992 and Mole 2011.
To make our discussion concrete, consider Simons and Chabris’s (1999) famous “Selective Attention Test” on youtube (see the link in Other Internet Resources). When subjects were asked to count passes of basketballs—spoiler alert!—a fair number failed to notice a person in a gorilla suit who came into the scene. Given how hard it is to track the passes of basketballs, it is natural to assume that the non-noticers were attending only to the basketballs, and did not attend to the person in the gorilla suit. Now suppose that some of non-noticers still did experience a person in a gorilla suit in the scene, as a person in a gorilla suit. According to the Attention Needed view, their inattentive experience cannot provide them with justification to believe that someone’s there in a gorilla suit. According to the Attention Optional view, their inattentive experience might still provide them with justification to believe that someone’s there in a gorilla suit.
Both views have their attractions. Typically, if you look carelessly at a scene, your experience will put you in a worse epistemic position if you look attentively at the scene. Perhaps if attention is fully gone but experience remains, experience no longer provides justification.
On the other hand, you can have evidence you don’t notice you have, and this point might favor the Attention Optional view. Consider everyday cases of “change blindness” discussed by Dretske 2004. For example, your friend gets a haircut, and asks you “do I look different?” You are stumped. On Dretske’s account, you might still have a perfectly accurately experience of how his hair now looks. Here your experience plausibly gives you justification to believe that your friend got a haircut (when combined with your background beliefs). You also fail to notice that your experience gives you justification to believe your friend got a haircut. If experiences provide un-noticed evidence, such cases are arguably good precedents for the sorts of cases allowed by the Attention Optional view. (For striking cases of change blindness, see the link in Other Internet Resources.)
For further discussion of the potential epistemic roles of attention, see Campbell 2002, 2011; Roessler 2011; Smithies 2011; Wu 2014; and Silins and Siegel 2014.
According to one empiricist tradition, experience functions as a mirror, reflecting what is before the subject, without any manipulation by the subject’s mind. Given that experience is supposed to not be influenced by one’s theories or expectations, it is thereby supposed to be in an optimal position to confirm or disconfirm hypotheses about the world. According to a wide range of philosophers and scientists, such a picture of the nature of experience is mistaken, putting limitations on the ability of experience to justify belief. In the philosophy of science, the challenge has been put in terms of the “theory-dependence of observation”, and the implications thereof. In more recent epistemology and philosophy of mind, the challenge has been put in terms of “cognitive penetration” or “top-down” effects and the implications thereof.
To survey the debate, we’ll start with the philosophy of mind by considering potential examples of the phenomenon, and we will then turn to questions in epistemology.
One potential source of examples comes from ambiguous figures such as the Necker cube (Hanson 1958; Kuhn 1962; Churchland 1979, 1988).
Figure 4. Necker Cube [4]
You can see this figure as a downward-tilted cube with the left face closest to you, or as an upward-tilted cube with the right face closest to you. Critics dispute whether such examples support any thesis of theory-dependence of observation. An alternative response is that you experience the figure in different ways merely because you attend to different parts of the figure at different times. Here the difference in your experience is not explained by differences in what theory you hold (Fodor 1984).
Theorists such as Hanson, Kuhn and Churchland also made much of work by so-called “New Look” psychologists such as Bruner and Postman. Consider for instance Bruner and Postman’s classic 1949 experiment involving anomalous playing cards. In this experiment, subjects were briefly shown the following sort of card:
What did you just see? When subjects were exposed to this sort of card, many reported it to be a six of hearts. The card is actually a red six of spades.
One might claim that the card looked to you the way red sixes of hearts look to you. However, there is much skepticism about whether there is an effect here on perceptual experience itself (Fodor 1983; Pylyshyn 1999). Perhaps the card fails to look like a red six of hearts to you, and you simply jumped to the conclusion that it is a red six of hearts when you form your belief. The effect might merely have been on beliefs formed on the basis of perceptual experience.
The current debate about cognitive penetration is informed by more recent experiments in psychology. For a case of a top-down effect in the current literature, consider “memory color” in Hansen et al.’s banana (2006). When subjects were asked to adjust an image of a characteristically yellow object until it was achromatic, they overcompensated by adjusting until the image was slightly bluish. Subjects did not overcompensate with objects that were not characteristically yellow. The type of case presented by Hansen et al. is much harder to explain away as not really involving top-down effects than those in the classic philosophy of science literature. (For related examples, see Delk and Fillenbaum 1965 or Olkkonen, Hansen, and Gegenfurtner 2008. For further discussion of whether and how there might be top-down effects on perception, see Macpherson 2012, Deroy 2013, Firestone and Scholl 2016; Green 2020).
Let us now turn to the epistemology of cases of cognitive penetration.
It’s not clear whether all cases of top-down effects are problematic for perceptual justification. Consider the possibility of top-down effects from expertise. For example, perhaps the expert radiologist sees more than the novice when looking at an x-ray, and perhaps the expert chess-player sees more than the novice when looking at a chessboard in mid-game (see the papers in Ericsson 2006 for discussion of such examples). Further, suppose that the expertise examples are genuine cases of top-down influence. Here the expert is presumably at an epistemic advantage thanks to top-down effects, where her experience justifies her with respect to those contents that her experience has thanks to her cognitive background (Siegel 2012).
To see why some cases of top-down effects might be epistemically problematic, consider Siegel’s (2012) hypothetical case of “Angry Looking Jack”. Suppose that Jill antecedently has an unjustified belief that Jack is angry at her. The next time she sees him, he does look angry to her—as a result of a top-down effect from her belief. In response to her experience, Jill then reaffirms her belief. Is she now justified in believing that Jack is angry at her? (Markie 2005 presents a related example of a gold prospector whose wishful thinking makes a nugget visually seem to be gold).
If you are inclined to deny that Jill’s belief is justified, you could appeal to an intuition that Jill is not justified by her experience in believing that Jack is angry at her (Siegel 2012). But others may not share the intuition.
Another strategy is to give a further argument that Jill is not justified by her experience in believing that Jack is angry at her. For arguments that appeal to an analogy with the unjustified formation of a belief on an unjustified belief, see McGrath (2013) and Siegel (2013) (Teng 2021 critically responds). For an argument that appeals to an analogy with the unjustified formation of beliefs on the basis of emotion, see Vance (2014).
How to cite this entry. | |
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society. | |
Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). | |
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database. |